The Ethics of Hunting: Evaluating Harm, Motivation, and Moral Weight
- Danielle Choi
- Jul 21
- 4 min read
Whether hunting is moral has long been a point of contention in environmental ethics. While some view it as an act of barbarism, others see it as a necessity for ecological balance or cultural preservation. Rather than deeming hunting entirely permissible or impermissible, I argue that its moral evaluation must be contingent on the purpose, consequence, and context of the act. Drawing on the categories laid out in “Is Hunting Moral? A Philosopher Unpacks the Question,” this essay will explore the three major motivations behind hunting—therapeutic, subsistence, and sport—and assess their moral implications. In doing so, I will also address public reactions to notable examples such as the killing of Cecil the Lion, the rhino hunts in Zimbabwe, and the dolphin slaughter in The Cove, to illustrate the broader cultural and ethical tension surrounding the practice.
The philosopher featured in the article identifies three central justifications for hunting: therapeutic, subsistence, and sport. Therapeutic hunting aims to preserve ecosystems or species by removing invasive or dangerous animals. Subsistence hunting focuses on human nourishment and survival, often embedded within cultural or Indigenous practices. Sport hunting, by contrast, is motivated by personal enjoyment and thus attracts the greatest moral scrutiny.
At the core of this discussion lies the concept of harm, particularly as it pertains to sentient beings. Since animals possess the capacity to suffer, the deliberate infliction of pain upon them for non-essential reasons appears intuitively immoral. However, the argument that any act of hunting is inherently unethical collapses under deeper scrutiny. If we reject harm to animals in principle, must we also reject predation in the natural world? Nature abounds with suffering—starvation, disease, and competition are all part of ecological life. Therefore, it is not sufficient to condemn hunting based solely on the harm it causes; rather, the harm must be considered in proportion to its justification and consequence.
The moral complexity of therapeutic hunting becomes apparent in the example of Zimbabwe’s rhino hunts. While it may seem unethical to allow hunters to kill endangered animals, the context reveals deeper nuance. In the podcast detailing these hunts, the term “problem rhinos” is used to describe particularly aggressive individuals who threaten both human lives and wildlife stability. These hunts are conducted under tightly regulated conservation tags that fund wildlife programs, support local economies, and ensure that the species as a whole can thrive. Though the visual of a dying rhino—described as a slow and uncomfortable process—triggers moral discomfort, the net benefit must be weighed. If the removal of one problematic rhino leads to the conservation of others and generates financial aid for impoverished communities, then the act may be morally permissible under the therapeutic category.
The same cannot be said for sport hunting, which raises questions about the hunter’s moral character. The killing of Cecil the Lion by trophy hunter Walter Palmer sparked global outrage, particularly among Western audiences. Although Palmer’s hunt was legally sanctioned through a conservation tag, the moral debate surrounding the event transcended legality. In her article, Goodwell Nzou, a Zimbabwean scholar, challenges the West’s fixation on African wildlife by highlighting a double standard: “Don’t tell us what to do with our animals when you allowed your own mountain lions to be hunted to near extinction.” Nzou’s critique underscores an often-overlooked dynamic—the disproportionate value Western societies place on the aesthetic and symbolic appeal of animals like lions, rather than the practical realities facing local populations. Palmer’s case demonstrates that even legally justified hunts can appear immoral if the motivation is personal satisfaction rather than communal or ecological good.
The dolphin slaughter depicted in The Cove offers a starkly different ethical scenario. While the Japanese fishermen claim cultural tradition and subsistence as justification, closer examination reveals a profit-driven motive. The dolphins are either sold to marine parks or slaughtered for meat—meat that, due to high mercury levels, is harmful to consumers. Here, none of the three moral rationales for hunting apply: it is neither therapeutic, as it offers no benefit to the ecosystem; nor subsistence, as the meat is both toxic and unnecessary; nor sport, as the act is conducted covertly and without recreational context. Furthermore, the documentary reveals the high cognitive and emotional capacities of dolphins—one scientist even noted their attempts to communicate as they awaited slaughter. The intentional and unnecessary harm inflicted on such sentient beings, solely for financial gain, renders the act morally indefensible.
The public’s differing reactions to these examples also reveal a troubling inconsistency. Why are Western audiences more outraged over the death of a lion than over the systemic suffering of factory-farmed animals or the slaughter of dolphins? This may reflect an unconscious bias toward animals that are charismatic, large, or aesthetically pleasing. Yet if we are to construct a truly consistent environmental ethic, we must move beyond surface-level emotional responses and examine the underlying motivations and outcomes of human actions toward animals.
Ultimately, the morality of hunting cannot be reduced to a binary judgment. It is not the act of hunting itself, but the motivation behind it, the method by which it is done, and the consequences it brings, that determine its ethical standing. Therapeutic and subsistence hunting can, under the right circumstances, be morally defensible. Sport hunting and profit-driven slaughter, however, require a more critical lens, as they often reflect a disregard for both human and animal dignity. Rather than react with moral absolutism, we should engage with hunting as a practice shaped by context, intent, and consequence—recognizing that our treatment of animals ultimately mirrors our respect for ourselves and the world we inhabit.
Recent Posts
See AllIs it ever morally justifiable to let people die in order to protect natural values? At first glance, the answer seems clear: human life...
Thomas Hill presents a situation where his neighbor cuts down an avocado tree and covers the ground in his backyard with asphalt. The...
Speciesism is a “prejudice involving a preference for one’s own kind based on a shared characteristic that in itself has no moral...
Comments