Feeding People or Saving Nature?
- Danielle Choi
- Jul 21
- 3 min read
Is it ever morally justifiable to let people die in order to protect natural values? At first glance, the answer seems clear: human life must come first. However, this intuition becomes ethically unstable when short-term efforts to meet human needs result in long-term ecological degradation that ultimately undermines human well-being. Although feeding people is a serious moral concern, there exists a tipping point at which prioritizing immediate human survival at the expense of nature causes greater harm—both to people and the planet. At that juncture, preserving nature becomes not only defensible but essential.
Holmes Rolston III explores the deep-rooted belief that feeding the hungry is a sacred duty. This value is reflected in religious texts and humanitarian rhetoric. Yet, Rolston challenges the idea that feeding people has always been society’s highest priority. If that were true, human history would have favored nutrition above all else. Instead, resources have consistently gone into constructing religious institutions, sponsoring art, building schools, and funding military expansion. These examples suggest that human flourishing extends beyond basic sustenance, and that societies regularly accept moral trade-offs in the interest of long-term or intangible values.
Contemporary policy decisions also demonstrate a willingness to accept human death as collateral for broader benefits. Increasing highway speed limits leads to thousands of additional fatalities globally, yet governments justify the change based on economic efficiency. Similarly, funding for the arts, military, or space programs often takes precedence over hunger relief. If we tolerate human deaths in these contexts, why should environmental protection be held to a stricter moral standard?
This question becomes more urgent in light of escalating overpopulation. As the human population grows, so does the demand for food, water, and land. Meeting these needs often results in deforestation, biodiversity loss, and carbon emissions. In the short term, feeding people may seem like the moral choice—but doing so unsustainably accelerates environmental collapse. This paradox reveals the flaw in prioritizing present human needs without regard for long-term consequences. Eventually, the environment loses its capacity to support future generations, thereby harming more lives than it saves.
This critique also extends to John Broome’s economic framework, which relies on discounting future goods relative to present ones. Such a model treats present human benefits as inherently more valuable than the needs of future populations. However, irreversible environmental damage—such as species extinction or resource depletion—makes future goods more, not less, valuable. Inverting this discounting logic highlights the importance of protecting endangered species and fragile ecosystems, such as Madagascar’s forests or India’s tigers, even when immediate human needs exist. Preserving these systems today may be the only way to ensure stable living conditions tomorrow.
Assuming individuals have duties in response to climate change, how should these be met? Rolston identifies three root problems: overpopulation, overconsumption, and under-distribution. These are not merely policy issues; they stem from collective individual behavior. No single act of recycling, diet change, or emission reduction will solve the climate crisis, but broad adherence to environmentally responsible behavior can mitigate large-scale harm. Individual duty matters precisely because environmental degradation is the sum of many personal choices.
Moreover, our discomfort with causing species extinction reflects an implicit moral understanding. Even absent utility, we hesitate to extinguish species because we view them as inherently valuable—an intuition often reinforced by religious belief in a divinely ordered natural world. Allowing species to vanish for short-term benefit reflects a disregard for the ecological complexity that underpins all life, including our own.
Therefore, while feeding the hungry is a moral priority, it is not absolute. When environmental degradation threatens future human flourishing, preserving nature is not a competing interest—it is a precondition for continued survival. The challenge lies in balancing present obligations with long-term consequences. By recognizing the ethical significance of future goods, embracing personal responsibility, and questioning policies that treat nature as expendable, we can begin to construct a moral framework that supports both human dignity and environmental integrity.
Recent Posts
See AllWhether hunting is moral has long been a point of contention in environmental ethics. While some view it as an act of barbarism, others...
Thomas Hill presents a situation where his neighbor cuts down an avocado tree and covers the ground in his backyard with asphalt. The...
Speciesism is a “prejudice involving a preference for one’s own kind based on a shared characteristic that in itself has no moral...
Comments